Medicolegal Aspects in Obstetrics and Gynecology Gita Ganguly Mukherjee, Narendra Malhotra, Bhasker Pal, Basab Mukherjee
INDEX
×
Chapter Notes

Save Clear


1General2

Ethics in Medical PracticeCHAPTER 1

SN Tripathy,
Ajit Kumar Sarkar
 
‘ETHICS AND SCIENCE MUST SHAKE HANDS’
Society as a whole is always guided by ethics, and it is more so in case of health care providers. Ethics in global culture means the disciplined study of morality, a concept that encompasses right and wrong behavior, i.e. what we should or should not do, good and bad character (virtues and vices). The fundamental question that ethics addresses is, What is moral? This question involves two other questions: What should our behavior be and what virtues should be cultivated in our moral lives? For centuries the basis for what morality should be in clinical practice has been the obligation to protect and promote the interest of the patients. This ethical obligation must be made more specific to be used clinically. We can accomplish this goal by examining two perspectives, that of the physician and that of the patient. In the history of medical ethics, the older of these two perspective is that of the physician. Based on scientific knowledge, shared clinical experience, and a careful unbiased evaluation of the patient, the physician can identify those clinical strategies that most likely will serve the health-related interests of the patient and those that will not. The ethical principle of beneficence structures this clinical perspective on the interest of the patient. The two most frequently referred to systematic accounts of what make actions morally right or wrong (or theories of obligation) are: Deontological theories—some principles are intrinsically right regardless of resulting consequences.1 Consequentalist theories—greatest happiness of greatest number.2 Principles of these two theories are same.
 
HISTORY
The ethical doctor adheres to beneficence. Beneficence-based clinical judgment has got ancient roots. In India in 600 BC, Sushrut3 has laid 4down a set of rules, how the medical profession should behave (Table 1.1).
Table 1.1   The oath of initiation for medical study. (From Susruta Samhita 600BC)
Thou shalt renounce all evil desires, anger, greed, passion, pride, egotism, envy, harshness, untruth, indolence and other qualities that bring infamy upon oneself. Thou shalt clip thy nails and hair close, observe cleanliness, wear brown garment and dedicate thyself to the observance of truth, celibacy and the salutation to elders. Devoting thyself at my bidding movement, laying thyself down, being seated, taking thy meal and study, thou shalt be engaged in doing whatever is good and pleasing to me. If thou shouldst behave otherwise, sin will befall thee. Thy learning will go fruitless and will attain no popularity.
 If I do not treat you thee properly despite thy proper observance of these behests, may sin befall me and my learning will go fruitless.
 The twice born, the precepto, the poor, the friendly, the travelers, the lowly, the good and the destitute, these thou shalt when they come to thee, like thy own kith, relieve their ailments with thy medications, thus behaving good will befall you. Thou should not treat a hunter, bird catcher and a person doing sinful acts. Thus thy learning will attain popularity and will gain for thee friends, fame, righteousness, wealth and fulfillment.
Hippocratic oath4 is an oath traditionally taken by physicians pertaining to the ethical practice of medicine. It is widely believed that the oath was written by Hippocrates, the father of medicine, in the 4th century BC, or by one of his students. Although mostly of historical and traditional value, the oath is considered a rite of passage for practitioners of medicine, although it is not obligatory and no longer taken up by all physicians. Several parts of the oath have been removed or re-shaped over the years in various countries, schools, and societies as the social, religious, and political importance of medicine has changed. Most schools administer some form of oath, but the great majority no longer use the ancient version. The Hippocratic Oath has been updated by the declaration of Geneva as adopted by the third General Assembly of World Medical Association at Geneva, Switzerland, in September 1948 (Table 1.2) and the International Code of Medical Ethics as adopted by the general Assembly of World Medical Association held in London, in october1949. In the United Kingdom, the General Medical Council provides clear modern guidance in the form of its ‘Duties of a Doctor’ and ‘Good Medical Practice’ statements. Since then many modifications have been made over the years; in the 22nd World Medical Assembly Sydney, Australia, August 1968, and the 35th World Medical Assembly Venice, Italy, October 1983 and the last one being WMA General Assembly, Pilanesberg, South Africa, October 2006.5
Table 1.2   Declaration of Geneva
AT THE TIME OF BEING ADMITTED AS A MEMBER OF THE MEDICAL PROFESSION:
I SOLEMNLY PLEDGE to consecrate my life to the service of humanity; I WILL GIVE to my teachers the respect and gratitude that is their due; I WILL PRACTISE my profession with conscience and dignity; THE HEALTH OF MY PATIENT will be my first consideration; I WILL RESPECT the secrets that are confided in me, even after the patient has died; I WILL MAINTAIN by all the means in my power, the honor and the noble traditions of the medical profession; MY COLLEAGUES will be my sisters and brothers. I WILL NOT PERMIT considerations of age, disease or disability, creed, ethnic origin, gender, nationality, political affiliation, race, sexual orientation, social standing or any other factor to intervene between my duty and my patient; I WILL MAINTAIN the utmost respect for human life; I WILL NOT USE my medical knowledge to violate human rights and civil liberties, even under threat;
  • I MAKE THESE PROMISES solemnly, freely and upon my honor
Medical ethics since the 18th century is secular. By secular it means that medical ethics do not need to make references to God or revealed tradition, but only to what rational discourse produces, regardless of their personal religious and spiritual beliefs and can be reliably applied in clinical practice in diverse global cultures. The tradition and practices of medicine constitute an important and enduring source of morality for physicians. They provide a reference point for medical ethics in a very general abstract form. Providing a more concrete, clinically applicable account of physician's obligations in clinical practice is a central task of medical practice using ethical principles. In contrast to the principle of beneficence, there has been increasing emphasis in the global literature of medical ethics on the principle of respect for autonomy. This principle requires the health care provider to acknowledge and carry out value based preferences of the adult competent patient. The principle of respect for autonomy translates this fact into autonomy-based clinical judgement and enters clinical practice in way of informed consent.
 
BASIC MEANING OF ETHICS5
 
Aims of the Doctor
The medical practitioner ought to keep in mind four cardinal aims:
  • To preserve life
  • Effect the cure of the illness
  • Prevention of disease
  • Advancement of medical knowledge
 
To Preserve Life
Preserving life is the most important aim of the doctor. But in certain circumstances, it is a difficult question. The first question is when life 6begins, the second whom to sacrifice in a critical condition, mother or the fetus and the third is about euthanasia.
 
Euthanasia
How can euthanasia be defined, and what are the various terms linked to it? Euthanasia literally means good death (from the Greek, eu = Good, thantos = death). Euthanasia is the intentional killing, by act or omission, of a dependent human being for his or her alleged benefit, the key word being intentional. When the person who is killed has made and expressed a wish to be killed, it is termed voluntary euthanasia, When the person who is killed is not capable of giving permission, it is termed non-voluntary euthanasia. When the person who is killed has made and expressed wish not to be killed, it is termed involuntary euthanasia. When someone provides an individual with the information, guidance and means to take his own life, it is referred to as assisted suicide. When a doctor helps in this, it is physician assisted suicide. Causing a person's death by performing an action is called euthanasia by action. Euthanasia by ommission refers to intentionally causing death by not providing necssary and ordinary care or food and water. Some medical actions that are often labelled passive euthanasia are not a classic form, as the intention is not there. Euthanasia is not only for people who are terminally ill, the proactivists are replacing them as hopelessly ill, desperatly ill, etc.
 
The Indian Perspective: Sati, Samadhi and Prayoaveshan
Hinduism advocates the doctrine of rebirth and reincarnation. Religious scriptures use the metaphor of the immortal soul changing bodies the way human beings change their garments. With this background, perceptions are different in India about euthanasia. Both voluntary and involuntary euthanasia has been indirectly prevalent and rampant in India for centuries. Saints and sages used to take up Samadhi;Sati, where a wife jumps into the funeral pyre of her husband (Forced Euthanasia) and Prayoaveshan, voluntary cessation of nutrition which has religious sanctity. Currently under Indian Law, all forms of euthanasia are illegal and outlawed.6, 7
The key question which revolves around euthanasia is the patient's right to autonomy and choosing a dignified death and a physician's moral and medical duties especially at the end of life. This is a complicated, interdisciplinary debate spanning the areas of psychology, ethics, medicine, law and philosophy.7
 
Effect the Cure of the Illness
The real aim of the physician is to effect the cure of the illness. When a cure is not possible, the object should be to lessen suffering. A doctor must also aim to bring comfort to a patient. In the process of effecting a cure or relieving pain, a practitioner on account of the faith he inspires in his patient may by sympathetic care and by explaining the illness or disease bring solace to his patients. A doctor deals with human beings. His attitude, his way of handling a patient, his understanding of and his approach to human suffering all have a bearing on his ability to inspire confidence in the patient. He ought not to lose his temper and indulge in strong language. The professional man should first and foremost be a gentleman. In course of his practice the practitioner will come acroos many trying circumstances which call for self-control, hence the demeanour of the practitioner towards a patient must be cautious, sympathetic, friendly and helpful.
 
Prevention of Disease
Prevention of disease also is the aim of the doctor. The oft repeated quote “prevention is better than cure” still holds good. The present day physician is in a more enviable position than his forefathers as modern drugs have made it possible for the physician to prevent many diseases.
 
Advancement of Medical Knowledge
The fourth aim of the doctor is to help in the advancement of medical knowledge. If he has discovered something, however small, he should attempt to desseminate his knowledge, the best way is to publish it in medical journal. He must update his knowledge by attending CMEs and reading recent journals.
It is unethical for medical practitioners to cooperate with or obtain the cooperation of non-medical man with regard to their professional practice.
 
Refusal to Treat
The physician may choose whom he will treat and lay down terms of his service, but once he accepts the charge, it is his responsibility to exercise due care and diligence in the diagnosis and treatment using the best means and information avialable to him. He cannot give up the patient without his/her consent except for valid reasons such as that remedies other than prescribed by him are being used, his remedies and instructions are being ignored, he is convinced that the complaint of the patient is not genuine, the doctor himself for reasons of his own health is unable to attend the patient, etc.8
 
Consultation
There are occasions when a practitioner must advise his patient to consult another doctor as no medical practitioner can claim to be a specialist in every branch of medicine. The right of the patient to ask for a second opinion should as far as possible be respected. The family physician must suggest the name of the consultant, but in the event of a difference between him and the relatives, the choice of the relatives must prevail. Guidance regarding when to refer and the consultation is given in the principles of Medical ethics of the Indian Medical Association, the British Medical Association.8
 
Regarding Colleagues
It is an elementary rule of ethics that a doctor must not entice away patients from his colleagues and that he ought to behave towards them as he would have them behave towards him. The duties of doctors towards each other is described in detail in the International Code of Ethics.
Can a practitioner charge another practitioner for medical attendance on him? There is no rule that they should not charge each other for their services, but generally, it is considered a pleasure and privilege to give one's services freely to a professional brother, his wife and children and to a medical student. In the words of the Declaration of Geneva, ‘My colleagues will be my brothers.’
But in our opinion, this practice should change. Now the population of doctors are very vast. In this era of fast life nobody likes to give service without benefit. So, a doctor who becomes a patient is in a very awkward position and no one wants to take his responsibility. Taking fees from him and taking good care may be much better.
 
Fees
A practitioner's fee should be commensurate with the services rendered and the patient's ability to pay for his services, he expects to be reasonably compensated. What would be reasonable would depend upon the practitioners capability, training and experience and the current practice among his colleagues. Dichotomy or splitting of fees is unethical.
 
Medical Secrets
A medical practitioner is under obligation to his patient to preserve his secrets, but in a court of law even without the patient's consent, he is bound to answer questions relevant to the case under subpoena. Ethics on which medical opinion is divided are disclosure of veneral disease 9and HIV infection to the other partner. Some say secrecy must be maintained at any cost, their argument being, the basis of the science of medicine is the intimate relationship between the patient and the doctor.
 
Medical Experimentation
A written consent must be taken from the patient when experimentation is done on him or her. It would be unethical to do something mainly by way of experimentation, i.e. what is done is not strictly related to the cure of the patient. As soon as ill effect is noted, the experimentation must be stopped and the doctor should make efforts to see the ill effects be remedied. The case for and against experimentation on human beings is often discussed and argued.
 
Nursing Homes
A practitioner cannot name a private nursing home, dispensary or hospital on his own name. The advertisement should only contain the name, address, approach and facilities avilable and the type of patient the nursing home entertains. If assistants are there for help, the ultimate responsibility rests on the practitioner.
 
Prescription and Drugs
Drugs should be used only as therapeutic agents. A doctor prescribing narcotics ought to be extra-cautious and must not help the patient to induldge in them. A drug is not to be used because it is new when older ones are equally effective. The cost of the drug must be considered. The prescription should not be written in secret formulae.
 
Soliciting Clients and Advertisements
A practitioner should avoid soliciting practice either personally or by advertisements in newspaper, by playcards or by distribution of circulars, cards or handbills, by giving as commission percentage of fees received or employing or sanctioning employment of agents or canvasses for the purpose of procuring patients. The scale of fees can be put in the chamber of the practitioner, not outside.
Publishing or sanctioning the publication of reports of cases or operations or other treatments or letter of thanks from patients or of any kind of laudatory notices with regard to professional matters in other than professional newspapers or journal is objectionable. Discussing the futility or utility of different methods of diagnosis or treatment of diseases in lay press in the name of the doctor is unethical. Ethics do not prohibit publication in lay press, even under a practitioner's own name, matters 10of public health interest and general articles which promote hygienic living, nor does it prohibit public lectures by practitioners for the same purpose. It is unethical to permit the printing of one's name in telephone directory in types dissimilar to others. However, one can prefix the ‘Dr’ before a practitioner's name in telephone directory.
No medical practitioner should make use of an unduly large sign board. The board should never indicate more than the name, degree or diploma and rank or title with the bare detail of any line of practice.
 
How much a Doctor should Tell?
What is psychologically advisable in a particular situation is ethically also correct. Not disclosing certain items to the patient can best be judged only from what effect the disclosure would have on the patient. In modern days when the information on diseases is just a key away, whether to divulge all information should be kept in mind. How much should be told to the patient depends on the patient's intelligence, his ability to appreciate what is told to him, his education and his nervous and psychological attitude in the matter. If the doctor decides not to tell a patient regarding a fatal disease from which the patient is suffering, he should nevertheless freely and frankly inform the patient's relatives about the disease. This helps to safeguard the patient's interests, he can make a will, arrange his affairs, etc.
These ethics were there and almost all doctors from the day they enter the medical profession practice it. But now ethics has been transferred into a field on its own rights, like laparoscopic procedures. Formerly the almost exclusive domain of the physicians, medical ethics also known as bioethics, is now dominated by moral philosophers, theologists, lawyers and sociologists who advise the physicians on what they should do or should not do, and how they should act. During the last 20 years most medical schools have introduced courses on ethics into their curriculum, many hospitals have formed ethics committees and the literature is flooded with bioethical topics.
 
Why Ethical Issues are so Important?
Ethical issues have become important and the recent press headlines about euthanasia, destruction of frozen embryo, refusal to fund marrow transplant, controversy on stem cell research and genetic research, organ donation and transplantation etc prove that. There are advances in medical technology and each new technology brings its own ethical issues. Society as a whole is now better informed. Doctors are involved in management, and there is the big question of public funding.11
 
PRINCIPLES OF ETHICS
The four Principle approach, other wise known as Principlism was formulated as a basis for working out practical solutions for problems in medical ethics. They are beneficence, non-maleficence, autonomy, Justice. Later on Truth telling, Confidentiality and Preservation of life were added to the principles.
 
Beneficence
Beneficence is to act in the best interests of the patient, and to balance benefits against risks. In medicine, the ethical principle of beneficence requires the physician to act in a way that is reliably expected to produce the greater balance of clinical benefits over harms for the patient.9 Putting this ethical principle into clinical practice requires making it specific to clinical practice.10 It makes an important claim to interpret reliably the health-related interest of the patient from the perspective of medicine. This perspective is provided by accumulated scientific research, clinical experience and reasoned response to uncertainty. This perspective should not be understood to be the function of an individual physician's clinical perspective and therefore should not be based merely on the clinical impression or intuition of an individual physician. Beneficence-based clinical judgment should be the function of a rigorous clinical perspective that appeals to the best available evidence and its clinical application to a particular case. It identifies the benefits that can be achieved for the patient in clinical practice based on the competencies of medicine. The benefits that medicine is competent to seek for patients are the prevention and management of disease, injury, handicap, and unnecessary pain and suffering and the prevention of premature or unnecessary death.
 
Autonomy
Autonomy means to respect the right of the individual. Capacity to think, decide, and take action about her own life in the context of respect for everyone else involved is autonomy. If there is mental incompetence, there is no autonomy. Respect for autonomy enters the clinical practice by the informed consent process. This process usually understood to have three elements, disclosure by the physician to the patient of adequate information about the patient's condition and its management, understanding of that information by the patient and a voluntary decision by the patient to authorize or refuse treatment. Beacause each patient's perspective on her interest is a function of her values and beliefs, it is impossible to specify the benefits and harms of autonomy-based clinical judgement in advance. There is always a debate about autonomy and paternalism. When the patient is autonomous, if paternalism creeps in, any procedure may be questionable.12
 
Nonmaleficence
It means that the physician should prevent causing harm and is best understood as expressing the limits of beneficence. This is commonly known as ‘Primum non nocere’ or first do no harm. Then, seek to prevent it. But there is always an inherent risk of paternalism in beneficence-based clinical judgment. If it is mistakenly considered to be the sole source of moral responsibility and therefore moral authority in medical care, it invites the physician to conclude that beneficence-based judgments can be imposed on the patient in violation of her autonomy. Paternalism should always to be avoided in medical practice.
The preventive ethics response to this inherent paternalism is for the physician to explain the diagnostic, therapeutic, and prognostic reasoning that leads to his or her clinical judgment so that the patient can assess that judgment for herself. In clinical practice, the physician should disclose and explain to the patient the major factors of this reasoning process, including matters of uncertainty. In neither medical law nor medical ethics does this require that the patient be provided with a complete medical education. Beneficence-based clinical judgment usually results in the identification of a clinical strategy that protects and promotes the health of the patient. This in turn provides an important preventive ethics antidote to paternalism by increasing the likelihood that one or more of these medically reasonable, evidence-based alternatives will be acceptable to the patient. This also increases patient compliance, and a better informed decision about whether to seek a second opinion or not.11
 
Justice
Justice signifies, to treat patients fairly and without unfair discrimination, there should be fairness in the distribution of benefits and risks. It raises many questions like how to care for scarce health care resources and how to distribute them. Medical needs, and medical benefits should be properly weighed. Discrimination against underprivileged should be avoided.
 
Confidentiality
Confidentiality is the basis of trust between doctor and patient.12, 13 By acting against this principle one destroys the patient's trust. Breaches of confidentiality can lead to breakdown of the patient-doctor relationship, lack of confidence and trust in other doctors, failure by patient to seek future medical treatment as a result of which their health may suffer, and can lead to disciplinary action against the doctor and civil action for 13compensation., But there is clash, i.e. when confidentiality would harm others. The points against confidentiality are lay patients unable to cope with data, opinions (not facts) cause anxiety, and accuracy improves by sharing information. The supporters of confidentiality claim that, data belongs to the patient and should not be shared with others.
Access to records also raises many questions, like which records are covered, does it matter when the record was made, who can apply, must copies be given if requested, access to records of deceased patients. There is a data protection act (1998). There are exceptions to confidentiality; if the patient has given written and valid consent, it can be given to other participating professionals. Where it is undesirable to seek patient's consent, information can be given to a close relative, to a statutory request, when ordered by court, for public interest and for approved research. The other question is, should patients have access to their notes?
 
ETHICAL DECISIONS AND THE REPRODUCTIVE HEALTH OF WOMEN
In obstetrics and gynecology, ethical issues have arisen out of social concerns about abortion, fetal research, medically assisted procreation, genetic engineering and conflict of interest between the pregnant woman and the fetus she carries. Now it has become virtually impossible to practice any branch of medicine without refering to ethical matters. If the patient refuses to accept the alertnatives supplied in beneficence-based clinical judgement, the physician is ethically and in most part of the world legally obligated to engage in what is known as informed refusal. The matter of informed refusal is very clear. The risks and benefits are explained to the patient in detail and they should be thoroughly documented in the notes of the patient.
 
Ethics in Gynecologic Practice
Beneficence-based and autonomy-based clinical judgements in gynecological practice are usually in harmony, like management of ruptured ectopic pregnancy. Sometimes, they may come into conflicts. In such a situation, one should not override the other. Their differences must be negotiated in clinical judgement and practice to determine which management strategies protect and promote the patients interests. In the techniqual language of ethics, it is medical ethical principles as prima facie or potentially overridable in nature.14
 
Ethics in Obstetric Practice
There are obvious beneficence-based and autonomy-based obligation to the pregnant patient. While the physician's perspective on the pregnant 14woman's interest provides the basis of beneficence-based obligations, her own perspective on those interests provides the basis for autonomy-based obligations. Because of an insufficiently devoloped central nervous system, the fetus cannot meaningfully be said to possess values and beliefs. Thus, there is no basis for saying that the fetus has a perspective on its interest. Therefore, there is no autonomy-based obligation to the fetus. The physician, however, has a perspective on the fetus's health-related interests and can have beneficence-based obligations to the fetus, but only when the fetus is a patient. But there are conflicts among ethical obligations, and they can be divided into four groups:
  1. Conflicts between maternal autonomy-based obligations of the physician and maternal beneficence-based obligations of the physician.
  2. Conflicts between fetal beneficence-based obligations of the pregnant woman and fetal beneficence-based obligations of the physician.
  3. Conflicts between maternal autonomy-based obligations of the physician and fetal beneficence-based obligation of the physician.
  4. Conflicts between maternal beneficence-based obligations and fetal beneficence-based obligations of the physician.
The ethical concept of the fetus as a patient is essential to obstetric clinical judgement and practice. A huge world literature has accumulated about the subject. Fetus as a patient depends on its moral status and when the moral status of the fetus starts is again controversial.14 Most people agree that the moral status attributed to the fetus is, when it is reliably expected later to achieve independent moral status as a child and person. If a fetus is viable, then there is beneficence-based obligation by the physician. When the fetus is a patient, directive counseling for fetal benefit is ethically justified and they are: recommending against termination, recommending for or against aggressive treatment for the benefit of the fetus. Directive counseling for fetal benefit should always occur in the context of balancing beneficence-based obligations to the fetus against beneficence-based and autonomy-based obligations to the pregnant woman. If a conflict arises, it should be solved by informed consent. To the pre-viable fetus, the pregnant woman's autonomy can confer the status of a patient. Counseling the pregnant woman regarding the management of her pregnancy at this stage is non-directive and this is also applicable in case of near viable fetus.
Apart from this big issue there are many other ethical issues in reproductive health, like induced abortion, infertility, HIV-infected person, genetics, ultrasonography, inclusion of ethics in postgraduate teaching, contraception in adolscent, embryonic stem cell research, ethics in in vitro fertilisation and embryo transfer, ovarian transplantation and many more issues. It is not possible to deal in detail about each topic in this article. Few of the topics are disccussed in brief.15
 
Ethics and Assisted Reproduction
It involves many issues like donor insemination, IVF, egg sharing, freezing and storing of embryos, embryo research and surrogacy. When Louise Joy Brown was born in 1978, the whole world was up in arms against it. Now IVF is commonplace. Still many ethical issues are involved in IVF. First there is a big question whether the in vitro embryo is a patient or not. It is appropriate to think that it is a pre-viable fetus and only the woman can give it the status of a patient. Hence, preimplantation diagnostic counseling is non-directive and counseling about how many embryos to be transferred should be evidence-based. Donor insemination raises the issue whether the child should be told about his genetic father or not. Egg sharing is also surrounded by many ethical issues. Ethics changes from time to time keeping pace with the changing social values, the surrogacy issue being an example. It was considered unethical few years back, now in a recent issue of India Today, a lengthy article has appeared supporting surrogacy with the name of a center, the photos of the physician and a number of happy surrogate mothers. One surrogate mother proudly claimed that, she had given her womb for rent three times to tide over her husband's financial crisis! To discuss all the ethical aspects of IVF is beyond the scope of this chapter. The reader is advised to consult a specific chapter devoted to this topic alone in the book.
 
Ultrasonography
There are many issues involved like competence and referal, disclosure, confidentiality and routine screening. The foremost issue is that the sonologist must be competent enough to give a definitive opinion. Now routine screening is adopted at 18–20 weeks, but prior to screening the prenatal informed consent for sonogram(PICS) must be taken. This includes informed consent about the disclosure. Strict confidentiality must be maintained.15
 
Genetics and Ethics
The process of genetic research raises difficult challenges particularly in the area of consent, community involvement and commercialisation. However, it must be recognised that many of these issues are not unique to genetics but rather represent variations and new twists on problems that arise in other types of research. Results of genetic research should be provided to subjects only if the tests have sufficient clinical validity. Results should never be disclosed to relatives, except in case of pedigree research. Policies regarding disclosure of test results should be included in the informed consent process. The genomic era poses challenges for 16the international community and research enterprises. Council for International Orgnisation of Medical Sciences (CIOMS) guideline should adress the ethical issues of genetics. The five ethical principles are required to guide the scope and practice of biomedical research, the goal being to care and protect greatest sources of human suffering and premature death and to relieve pain and suffering caused by the disorder.1618
 
Contraception and the Young Girl
Sometimes teenaged girls request for oral contraception. They are already in an active sexual relationship. They do not want that their parents should know about them taking contraceptives. What ethical consideration must guide the the physician in such a situation? Lord Fraser's recommendation is quite ethical and they are as follows:19
  • The doctor should assess whether the patient understands the advice.
  • The doctor should encourage parental involvement.
  • The doctor should take into account whether the patient is likely to have sexual intercourse without contraceptive treatment.
  • The doctor should assess whether the physical, mental health would likely to suffer, if contraceptive advice is not given.
 
Teaching Biomedical Ethics in Obstetrics and Gynecology Residency Training
Teaching biomedical ethics in residency training is a must. How to do, what to include is the duty of the faculty head and members of the faculty. The teaching should be built on ‘the five Cs’, i.e. clinically based teaching, cases as the teaching focus, continuous teaching through out the medical curriculum, co-ordinating ethics teaching with the trainee's other objectives and clinician's active participation both as co-instructors and role models for students. In our opinion, this should be taught to the students during the grand round, and in each case the ethical conflicts can be discussed in detail. As now most of the institurtions are having an ethical committee, it is easy to introduce the residents to biomedical ethics.20
 
Embryonic Stem Cell Research and Ethics
This involves many ethical issues and the first and foremost is, it is destroying a life by destroying the fertilised embryo. This raises the fundamental question of when life starts. Does human life begin at gastrulation (the next step after the blastula), at neurulation (formation of a primitive streak, the first signs of nervous system development), at quickening (the first signs of movement), or at the moment of sentience 17(consciousness)? When can an embryo first feel pain or first suffer? Indeed these are difficult questions. Somehow it seems inherently obvious that a wriggling fetus deserves more protection than a 100-cell embryo. Yet, the mere fact that an embryo has some capacity for development into a human being seems to endow it with a degree of moral respect not given simply to the pluripotent cells derived from it. The goal then should be to minimize the exploitation of human embryos at any stage of development. Beyond these considerations lie other, somewhat more concrete, ethical concerns. For example, due to the currently inefficient nature of the cloning process, the enormous number of anticipated technical hurdles, and the potential success of the method, an increased demand for oocytes will arise, raising issues of the exploitation of women across the world who will be paid or even coerced to donate eggs through procedures whose safety may be highly variable. Moreover, as the private sector weighs in, will therapeutic cloning be done with the best interests of embryo and patient alike, or will profit motives create a cost-benefit approach to cloning? Clearly these issues are on the horizon and they draw nearer as the potential for tissue regeneration increases through ES cell research. Hence, scientists must accept responsibility for therapeutic cloning. Fortunately, there is hope that research itself can find a way out of this dilemma. Straightforward issues of safety can be tackled by public funding into the risks involved in therapeutic cloning. Issues of female exploitation may be overcome by using animal eggs and to re-program adult human cells. Even more promising is the possibility of adult stem cell research.21, 22
 
The Impact of Law on Ethics
What is the relationship between law and ethics? Are they same? Ethics is involved with moral judgement, and the law, however, concerns public policy. At one level it defines what one can/cannot or must/must not do to avoid risk of legal penalty. For example, practitioners must at all times comply with the law in case of induced abortion. Ethics encompasses much more than law. Ethics can help to determine what is ‘right’, in the sense that it is ‘good’. The intention of law is to define what is ‘right’, in the sense that it is or is not permitted. It can be safely concluded that not only is ‘determining that some thing is unethical, neither a necessary nor a sufficient reason to make it illegal’, but also determining that some thing is lawful does not necessarily make it ethical. In many occasions the law assists clinical decision-making by setting parameters which helps both the patient and the physician.18
 
CONCLUSION
Ethics has now pervaded everyday life of the medical practitioner in a big way and in each and every step, he is beset with ethics. The physicians are taking ethical decisions every day since he or she qualifies, perhaps without knowing it. There is seldom an absolutely right or wrong decision. One is often trying to balance the greater good or lesser evil. Medical practice deals directly with humans, and interventions by medical professionals are often a matter of life and death. Medical knowledge and technology put practitioners in a position from where they can wield exceptional influence. Practitioners must balance this power with ethical conduct. Although some decisions must be reached quickly, the process of decision making should be no less rigorous. They are obliged to follow and respect the code of ethics which they vow to uphold when they graduate.
In our opinion, ethics is what a true doctor believes, that is the good of his patient, and nothing but the welfare of his patients. We conclude this chapter by quoting Sri Sri Ramakrishna Paramhans, the greatest sage of this era, about doctors.23
Doctors are of three classes. There are one class of doctors who when called in, look at the patient, feel his pulse, prescribe the necessary medicines and then ask the patient to take them. If the patient declines to do so, he goes away without troubling himself further about the matter. This is the lowest class. The second class of doctors not only ask the patients to take the medicine but they go further. They reason with him, counsel and leave no stone unturned to follow his advice. The third and highest type of doctors will use force on their patient in case their kind words fail. They will go the length of putting the medicine through his gullet.
The reader has to decide, what is his ethics.
REFERENCES
  1. Baron MW. Kantian ethics, In Baron MW, Pettit P, Stone M (Ed): Three Methods of Ethics—a debate. Blackwell Publishers  Oxford,  1997;3–91.
  1. Pettit P. Consequenatilist Perspective. In Baron MW, Pettit P, Stone M (Ed): Three Methods of Ethics—a debate. Blackwell Publishers  Oxford,  1997;92–174.
  1. Susruta Samhita, 600BC.
  1. Hippocrates, Oath of Hippocrates. In Temkin O, Temkin CL (Eds): Ancient Medicine, selected papers of Ludwig Edllstin. John's Hopkins University Press  Baltimore,  1976;6.
  1. Mehta HS. Medical ethics and etiquette, Medical Law and ethics in India. The Bombay Samachar Private Ltd.  March, 1963.
  1. Joshi Shalaka R. Whose life is it any way? The Evolving Face of Euthanasia. JAPI 2005;53:8.

  1. 19 The principles of Medical Ethics of the British Medical Association. BMJ, 1954; 1 (Suppl):page 77.
  1. Beuchamp TL, Childress JF. Principles of Biomedical Ethics 5th (Edn). New York University Press,  2001.
  1. Chevernak FA, McCullough LB. What is Obstetric ethics? Clinical Obstetrics and Gynaecology 1992;35(4):709–17.
  1. Chevernak FA, McCullough LB. Ethical issues in Obstetrics and Gynaecological practice (Eds). Progress in Obstetrics and Gynaecology. In John Stud, Seang Lin Tan, Frank A. Chevernak) 2007;17:1–14.
  1. General Medical Council. Duties of a doctor. Available from www.gmc-uk.org./standards, Accessed 2005;15.
  1. British Medical Association Ethics Department, Confidentiality, Medical Ethics. To day (2nd edn.) BMJ books  London,  2004;165–97.
  1. McCullough LB, Chevernak FA. Ethics in obstetrics and gynecology. Oxford University Press,  NewYork,  1994.
  1. Chevernak FA, McCullough LB. Ethical issues in Obstretic Ultrasonography. Clinical Obstetrics and Gynaecology 1992;35(4):758–762.
  1. Ellen Wright, Clayton EW. Genetic research towards international guidelines in biomedical research ethics. Updating international guidelines, Council for International Orgnisation of Medical Sciences (CIOMS)  Geneva,  2000;152–69.
  1. Walter L, Palmer JG. The ethics of human gene therapy. Oxford University Press,  NewYork,  1997.
  1. Hdizman NS, Watson MS (Eds). NIH-DOE. Working Group on ethical, legal and social implications on Human Genome research promoting safe and effective genetic testing in USA, Final reports of the Task Force on Genetic Testing, Bethesda, National Institute of Health,  1997.
  1. British Medical Association Ethics Department. Contraception, Abortion and Birth, Medical Ethics Today (2nd edn). BMJ books  London,  2004;224–68.
  1. Elkins TE. The Teaching of Biomedical Ethics in Obstetrics and Gynaecology residency programme. Clinical Obstetrics and gynaecology 1992;35:846–852.
  1. Canela Miguel Ruiz. Embryonic stem cell research. The relevance of ethics in progress of science. Medical Science Monitor 2002;8(5):21–26.
  1. David M Gilbert. The future of human embryonic stem cell research, adreesing ethical conflict with responsible scientific research. Medical Science Monitor 2004;10(5):99–103.
  1. Visit to Hindu Pandit and preacher. The condensed Gospels of Sri Ramakrishna. Page 195 published, Sri Sri Ramakrishna Math,  Madras.